The Language Hoax

No Comments

AUTHOR: John H McWhorter
TITLE: The Language Hoax
SUBTITLE: Why the World Looks the Same in Any Language
PUBLISHER: Oxford University Press
YEAR: 2014

REVIEWER: Peter Backhaus, Waseda University

SUMMARY

In the author’s own words, this book is a “manifesto” (ix) against the common
idea that language influences thought in any meaningful way. The main
arguments are briefly sketched in the introductory section, which describes
how this idea, best-known by the name of the Sapir-Whorf hypothesis, or, as
the author prefers, Whorfianism, has seen a revival in recent years. This
renewed interest in possible ways that our language might shape the way we
think has been triggered by a number of widely reported experimental studies
of so-called Neo-Whorfian researchers as well as popular science books on the
topic, most notably Deutscher’s Through the Language Glass (2010), to which
the present book’s subtitle alludes. While McWhorter in his introduction
expresses a largely favorable stance towards both the research itself and the
secondary literature on it, he criticizes their somewhat self-enlarging effect
in public discussion, to the extent that grammar can easily be conceived of as
a pair of glasses that produces a certain “‘wordview’” (xviii). To show that
this is a mistake is the main aim of this book.

Chapter 1, “Studies have shown,” reviews some of the recent research within
the Neo-Whorfian paradigm, including the frequently quoted Russian color
experiment (Winawer et al. 2007) that showed different reaction times in
recognizing shades of blue depending on the participants’ first language; a
controversially discussed study on Piraha numbers (Gordon 2004), which, as may
be added here, also became a topic on LINGUIST List (e.g. Everett 2004); and
Levinson’s (1996) well-known turning-the-tables research on language and
space, among others. McWhorter one by one refutes the purported implications
of these studies, on accounts which can be summarized as follows: “I’m unaware
of a Neo-Whorfian study in which neither of these things are true: (1) it’s
hard to say what it has to do with what it is to be human, or (2) the whole
claim is like saying a tribe’s lack of a word for _calf_ is why they don’t
raise cattle” (21).

Chapter 2 is called “Having It Both Ways”, and explains just why having it
both ways is a problem. McWhorter argues against the assumption of a
complementary relationship, in which cultural patterns influence linguistic
structures, which — once in place — will have repercussions on how speakers
of that language think. At this point, McWhorter introduces his “bubbles
theory,” which holds that certain linguistic structures “pop up” at a certain
point in time not because of cultural necessity but rather by mere chance. He
exemplifies this with a discussion of the occurrence of evidential markers
across the world’s languages, as well as the lack thereof, which he considers
at least as important. McWhorter demonstrates that it is extremely difficult
to find any regularities that could be attributed to the cultural environments
in which evidential markers tend to be found. In this respect, as the author
emphasizes, languages essentially differ from cultural things such as works of
art or architecture, which are deeply imprinted by culture. Unlike these,
however, and “that’s just it — languages are not things” (55).

Chapter 3 is a brief “Interregnum On Culture,” inserted by the author to make
clear that he does consider culture an important factor in the study of
language. The best point to bring this home is the grammatical complexity of a
given language, for which a statistically robust inverse correlation has been
found with the size of a society using that language (e.g., Sinnemäki 2009).
The whole point here, however, is that culture shapes language, not vice
versa. McWhorter also takes this chapter as an opportunity to distance himself
from the generative paradigm, whose continued predominance in linguistics he
sees as one likely reason for the “spontaneous affection for Whorfianism among
so many linguists and fellow travelers” (71).

In Chapter 4, called “Dissing the Chinese,” McWhorter introduces a somewhat
uglier face of Whorfianism. The chapter centers on Bloom’s (1981) monograph on
Chinese vs. English and how, in a wider sense, the two languages and their
differing degrees of grammatical complexity can very easily be read as
differences in cognitive patterns. The one difference between Bloom’s study
and most other studies in the Whorfian paradigm, is that in the case of
Chinese and the “telegraphic nature” of its grammar, it is the ‘other’
language that seems to be somewhat deficient, thus turning the benevolent
nature of the Whorfian mission on its head. In the author’s words: “If
languages that are bubbling over with fine-grained distinctions about
materials and the definiteness or actuality of things are windows into the
minds of their speakers, then what are we to suppose Chinese’s grammar tells
us about the minds of _its_ speakers?” (77, emphasis original). As McWhorter
points out, this Mr. Hyde edition of Whorf has not commonly been pursued by
researchers, and when it was, as in the case of Bloom, it met with severe
criticism.

In Chapter 5, McWhorter intentionally puts on a Whorfian hat to explore
“What’s The Worldview From English.” He provides a detailed analysis of the
sentence “Dey try to cook it too fast, I’m-a be eatin’ some pink meat!” (106)
and the underlying thought patterns one might excavate here — if only one
wanted to. No matter how hard we try, however, and McWhorter tries fairly
hard, he concludes that there is nothing about this sentence, or any other
sentence for that matter, to be reasonably identified as indicative of a
worldview shared by the speakers of English around the globe. At the same
time, he wonders whether such a worldview wouldn’t have been attestable much
more easily if the same sentence “had been uttered by a farmer in the hills of
Vietnam” (132).

Chapter 6 is the concluding chapter, and it is called “Respect for Humanity.”
Starting with the summarizing verdict that “the visceral appeal of Whorfianism
is not scientific” (136), it recaptures the main points of the argument from
the previous chapters and formulates three major problems of Whorfianism: (1)
the question of how to deal with less favorable features in the grammar or
vocabulary of a language, (2) a frequent exotification of other cultures
and/or their languages, and (3) the way (neo-)Whorfian ideas feed into public
discourse. Particularly with regard to this last point, the book, which
clearly addresses a non-scientific audience too, concludes with an appeal to
marvel at the universals that all languages share, rather than their
differences.

EVALUATION

_The Language Hoax_ is a well-written and stimulating book that asks
uncomfortable questions and turns common arguments on their head. The author
uses examples from an impressive number of languages across the globe to
provide counter-examples to claims that may easily be made (and occasionally
have been made) about the influence of language on thought. The discussion of
evidential markers in Chapter 2 is but one example of this. In addition, and
largely thanks to Chapter 3, McWhorter manages the difficult task of properly
positioning himself within the vast territory between the two extremes of
linguistic determinism and biolinguistics. His demonstration of what may
happen when we get real about Whorf — the inconvenient conclusions that would
need to be drawn with respect to grammatically less complex languages such as
Chinese (Chapter 4) and the all too shiny pearls of wisdom one could easily
come up with when searching for the worldview of _the_ English speaker
(Chapter 5) — is at once entertaining and enlightening.

A point of criticism is the book’s tendency to take issue with the idea of
“Whorfianism” as a whole, when there are actually rather distinct camps to be
considered: Whorf and his immediate research legacy, the Neo-Whorfians with
their more sound and sober approach to the topic, popular science books such
as Deutscher’s (2010), which the author keeps referring to throughout his
argument, and a general public (rightly) perceived to be all too easily
excited over linguistic differences and their possible impacts on culture and
thought. Of course McWhorter is well aware of these camps and sure to
disentangle them on various occasions (most notably in the introduction (xix)
and the conclusion (167)). However, frequent catch-all references to
“Whorfianism”, “the Whorfian”, or “Whorfian thought” at times leave it unclear
what exactly is the respective target of his criticism.

A second issue is McWhorter’s take on the empirical findings of Neo-Whorfian
research, particularly differences in reaction time for solving certain
experimental tasks and how these are pinned down to differing first languages
of the participants. While acknowledging the empirical validity of the
differences themselves, the author disregards these “nano-peep[s]” (87) as
“weensy bias that has nothing to do with anything any psychologist,
anthropologist, or political scientist could show us about how the people in
question manage existence” (28). Given the significance of mental chronometry
in so many scientific fields, including psychology, I’m not sure if his
somewhat ridiculed “_one tenth of a second_” (9, emphasis original) should be
done away with that easily.

Finally, and perhaps related to the second point, I was a little confused by
the following statement towards the end of the book: “the media as well as
academia continue to promulgate the idea that the question as to whether each
language is a special pair of lenses is an open one” (135). To the best of my
knowledge, this question is indeed an open one and, though I’m almost
uncannily in line with the author’s views on the topic, for the time being
should remain that way. That’s how science works.

As can be seen from the above, McWhorter’s thought-provoking manifesto
provides much stuff to think about and keep the discussion on language,
culture and thought going. It is suitable for both undergraduate and graduate
classes (I just did it in one of mine, in combination with Deutscher’s book),
to provide answers to the – yes, open – question of whether the world looks
different in other languages, or just the same in any language.

REFERENCES

Bloom, Alfred H. 1981. The Linguistic Shaping of Thought: A Study in the
Impact of Language on Thinking in China and the West. Hillsdale: Lawrence
Erlbaum.

Deutscher, Guy. 2010. Through the Language Glass: Why the World Looks
Different in Other Languages. London: Random House.

Everett, Daniel. 2004. Re: Mundurucu, Piraha Counting. LINGUIST List 15.3121.
https://linguistlist.org/issues/15/15-3121.html

Gordon, Peter. 2004. Numerical cognition without words: Evidence from
Amazonia. Science 306. 496-499.

Levinson, Steven C. 1996. Relativity in spatial conception and description. In
J.J. Gumperz & S.C. Levinson (eds.), Rethinking Linguistic Relativity (pp.
177-202). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Sinnemäki, Kaius. 2009. Complexity in core argument marking and population
size. In G. Sampson, D. Gil & P. Trudgill (eds.), Language Complexity As an
Evolving Variable (pp. 126-140). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Winawer J., Witthoft N., Frank M.C., Wu L., Wade A.R., Boroditsky L. 2007.
Russian blues reveal effects of language on color discrimination. Proceedings
of the National Academy of Sciences 104(19). 7780-7785.

ABOUT THE REVIEWER

Peter Backhaus is Associate Professor at Waseda University, Tokyo. His main
research interests are in sociolinguistics, pragmatics, and written language.

The Semantics-Pragmatics Controversy

No Comments

AUTHOR: Kristin  Börjesson
TITLE: The Semantics-Pragmatics Controversy
SERIES TITLE: Language, Context and Cognition 14
PUBLISHER: De Gruyter Mouton
YEAR: 2014

REVIEWER: Zhen-qiang Fan, Zhejiang Gongshang University

SUMMARY

“The Semantics-Pragmatics Controversy” is a timely and comprehensive addition
to the growing literature on the subject of the semantics-pragmatics
interface. It offers a critical comparison and evaluation of numerous
theoretical and empirical approaches concerning the distinction between
semantics and pragmatics. The book aims to answer three questions (p. 7):

1)  What is it that makes the standard notions of ‘literal meaning’ and
‘non-literal meaning’ inadequate and thus in need of revision?

2)  What exactly are the properties that characterize and differentiate
‘literal meaning’ and ‘non-literal meaning’ and how are these particular types
of meaning related to other types of meaning identified in the
semantics/pragmatics literature (e.g., conversational implicature, implicit
meaning aspects)?

3)  By which criteria should semantics and pragmatics be characterized and
differentiated, if not by the dichotomies traditionally used and under the
assumption that the two systems are involved in the determination of (at
least) three distinct meaning levels in interpretation?

The book contains five chapters. The first chapter is an introduction in which
the author illustrates some key pairs of notions for distinguishing semantics
and pragmatics, such as literal meaning vs. non-literal meaning, conventional
meaning vs. non-conventional meaning, and context-independent meaning vs.
context-dependent meaning. This chapter also presents the aims and the
organization of the book.

Chapter 2 argues against the traditional distinction of semantics and
pragmatics which is based on the dichotomy between literal and non-literal
meaning. More specifically, the author demonstrates the inadequacies of
viewing literal meaning as context-independent and conventional, and
non-literal meaning as context-dependent and non-conventional. It is pointed
out that (i) it is utterances (sentences used in context) rather than
sentences per se that may be used literally or non-literally; and (ii)
conventionality is not an ‘all-or-nothing’ concept but gradual, so neither
context-dependency nor conventionality are sufficiently precise for
distinguishing literal and non-literal meaning. Then the author discusses the
implications of these assumptions for the nature of lexical meaning by
reviewing a number of approaches to meaning in the lexicon, arguing for the
‘underspecification’ of lexical meaning. To support the assumption, empirical
evidence is reviewed. In the final section of this chapter, the author,
drawing on the notion of ‘stereotype’, explains why the traditional
distinction was assumed in the first place.

Having pointed out the context-dependency of literal meaning, Chapter 3 first
examines two approaches (namely those proposed by Grice and Bierwisch) which
distinguish two context-sensitive levels of meaning: the first level is ‘what
is said’ (Grice) or ‘utterance meaning’ (Bierwisch); the second level is ‘what
is meant’ (Grice) or ‘communicative sense’ (Bierwisch). Chapter 3 focuses on
the first level, while Chapter 4 of the book concentrates on the second level.
The main part of Chapter 3 discusses alternative approaches to the
characterization of ‘what is said’ or ‘utterance meaning’, offering a detailed
analysis of the processes involved in the interpretation of utterances as well
as the contexts used. Especially, this chapter explicates the controversy of
whether the processes contributing to what is said (utterance meaning) are
linguistically mandated and whether they should be taken to be independent of
speaker intentions. Besides theoretical discussion of the various views
concerning the nature of semantics and pragmatics components and their
interactions in utterance interpretation, the final part of this chapter also
present some empirical studies.

The first part of Chapter 4 concentrates on a series of phenomena (i.e.
metaphor, irony, conversational implicature, indirect speech act)
traditionally viewed as belonging to ‘what is meant’/ ‘communicative sense’,
aiming to find out which of these phenomena actually need a fully
propositional utterance meaning as their basis and what kind of contextual
information is required in the process of their interpretation. The author
argues that metaphor, along with metonymy, is related to sub-sentential parts
and belongs to utterance meaning, independent of the speaker’s intentions. In
contrast, the interpretation of irony needs an utterance level meaning as
basis. It also argues that similar to irony and different from metaphor,
conversational implicatures are based on some full utterance meaning and are
speaker intended. Moreover, the author argues against treating indirect speech
acts as conversational implicatures because they do ‘not seem to necessarily
involve a prior determination of a potential but non-fitting direct speech
act’ (p. 243). The second part of this chapter presents some debates on the
issue of whether it is necessary, possible or useful to differentiate between
the two pragmatically determined levels of meaning, i.e. ‘what is said’ vs.
‘what is meant’. The author argues that ‘such a differentiation is useful and
necessary’ (p. 9), although he admits that it is difficult to find the
criteria to be used in the differentiation.

After discussing in Chapters 3 and 4 a range of meaning aspects which do not
fit into the traditional literal/non-literal dichotomy, the fifth chapter
turns back to the basic question that Chapter 2 ends with, i.e. how literal
meaning and non-literal meaning should be best characterized if we want to
capture the various uses the two terms are put to. In this chapter, the author
gives a critical assessment of the alternative characterizations of literal
meaning and non-literal meaning before he presents his own proposal. It is
indicated that previous characterizations (Recanati and Ariel’s) of
literal/non-literal meaning trying to capture the various problematic
phenomena covered in Chapters 3 and 4 are inadequate in that they assume that
lexical meanings have full-fledged readings, somehow ignoring the
context-dependency of literal meaning. The chapter also discusses the nature
of contextual information in utterance interpretation and evaluates the
usefulness of contextual-dependence in distinguishing semantics from
pragmatics. Specifically, it is argued that the dichotomy of
context-dependence and context-independence can only be used to differentiate
‘linguistic semantics’ from ‘pragmatics’. The process of semantic
interpretation actually only applies to meaning representations that have
already been pragmatically enriched since the output of the
context-independent linguistic semantics component is only sub-propositional.
So what really distinguishes pragmatics and real semantics is the nature of
the processes constituting them: monotonic reasoning with non-defeasible
output in the case of real semantics, while non-monotonic reasoning with
defeasible output in the case of pragmatics (p.306). Finally, the author
claims that although both ‘what is said’/ ‘utterance meaning’ and ‘what is
meant’/ ‘communicative sense’ are context-dependent levels of meaning, they
should be differentiated from each other in that the latter take into
consideration assumptions concerning the speaker’s intentions in making the
particular utterance.

Finally, the last chapter summarizes the main general conclusions drawn from
each of the chapters of the book.

EVALUATION

Researchers interested in the semantics-pragmatics interface will undoubtedly
find this book to be a useful resource. This monograph stands out among the
numerous books or collections on the semantics-pragmatics distinction in that
it offers a comprehensive comparison and critical assessment of a wide range
of major approaches to this topic.

In terms of theory, the book not only argues against the role of some
traditional notions such as the literal/non-literal in distinguishing
semantics from pragmatics, but also critically evaluates various crucial
topics in the fields of both semantics and pragmatics, e.g. ‘what is said’ vs.
‘what is meant’, minimalism vs. contextualism, unarticulated constituents, ad
hoc concept, and free enrichment. Most importantly, the author explains how
these notions fit into the whole picture of the semantics/pragmatics
controversy. Apart from reviewing existing approaches, the author also makes
his own theoretical contribution to the issue at hand. For example, in the
final part of Chapter 5 he presents his own characterization of the semantics
vs. pragmatics distinction, which does not refer  to (non-)literal meaning or
context-(in)dependence.

Moreover, besides covering some traditional pragmatic phenomena (speech act,
conversational implicatures, generalized implicatures, etc.), the issues of
metaphor and metonymy are also addressed. As is known, metaphor and metonymy
are the common research concern of both pragmatics and cognitive linguistics.
It is argued elsewhere that relevance theory and cognitive linguistics are
complementary in explaining the mechanisms of metaphor and metonymy (Tendahl
and Gibbs 2008; Tendahl 2009; Ruiz de Mendoza Ibanez and Hernandez 2003). This
book goes beyond relevance theory and once again shows the cross-fertilization
between pragmatics and cognitive linguistics by giving a broader picture of
the semantic or pragmatic relevance of metaphor and metonymy.

Another strength of the book is that, in addition to theoretical speculations
and linguistic or discursive methods, the book also considers empirical data
in disciplines such as psycholinguistics and neurolinguistics. For instance,
in Chapter 2, a whole section is dedicated to empirical studies to prove that
lexical meaning should be characterized by underspecification and that
‘semantic processes of meaning construction should be differentiated from
pragmatically based plausibility checks’ (p. 8). And chapter 3 draws on some
experimental research in discussing ‘minimal proposition’ vs. ‘propositional
proposition’ (pp.147-154). In the future we would like to see more empirical
studies concerning his own proposals.

Overall, this book is a valuable resource and highly recommended to
researchers and novices in the areas of semantics, pragmatics, discourse
analysis, cognitive linguistics, and philosophy of language.

REFERENCES

Ruiz de Mendoza Ibanez, F. J. and Hernandez, L. P. (2003). Cognitive
Operations and Pragmatic Implication. In K. Panther and L. Thornburg (Eds.)
“Metonymy and Pragmatic Inferencing” (23-49). Amsterdam: John Benjamins
Publishing Company.

Tendahl, M. (2009). “A Hybrid Theory of Metaphor: Relevance Theory and
Cognitive Linguistics”. London: Palgrave Macmillan.

Tendahl, M. & Gibbs, R. W. (2008). Complementary perspectives on metaphor:
Cognitive linguistics and relevance theory. “Journal of Pragmatics” 40(11),
1823-1864.

ABOUT THE REVIEWER

Fan Zhen-qiang is a lecturer in linguistics at Zhejiang Gongshang University
in Hangzhou, China. He obtained his doctoral degree in the Center for the
Study of Language and Cognition, Zhejiang University, China. In 2008, he was a
visiting PhD at the Utrecht Institute of Linguistics (Uil-Ots), Utrecht
University, the Netherlands. His research interests lie in the areas of
cognitive linguistics and pragmatics.

Get Adobe Flash player